Squaring the Circle; Pi; Infinite Series THE NUMBER PI
Source: www.squaringthecircle.com, contact iterate@aol.com "This idea of a construction in steps that gets closer and closer to pi is a delightful idea, certainly new to me." --- Martin Gardner In
the mansions of mathematics today there is no room for one who still
thinks about the most famous problem of all time - squaring the circle.
For one hundred and ten years mathematicians have been convinced that
the nearly four thousand year old problem of squaring the circle is
sufficiently understood and that it is insoluble. With a prickliness
perhaps betraying some lingering anxiety, anyone who wastes further
time on the puzzle is regarded as mathematically incompetent.
Quietly
demurring from this starkly intimidating judgment stands ancient Greek
civilization itself. They were an extraordinary people, naming whole
branches of knowledge we venerate. Hardly the kind to waste their time
on a fool's errand. One can only marvel at the work of Apollonius of
Perga (247 - 205 BC) on conic sections. What impelled this great mind
to master such an obscure subject that would have no utility for
eighteen hundred years. And then we move forward and study Isaac
Newton's (1642 -1727) Principia Mathematica (1687) and realize that he
could not have made his discoveries about centripetal forces if he did
not have the principles of the ellipse, parabola and hyperbola with
which to build on Johannes Kepler's (1571-1630) interpretation of Tycho
Brae's (1546 -1601) naked eye measurements of the motions of the
planets. And that Kepler himself first needed Apollonius' conics to
derive his laws of planetary motion from Brae's data. From this rich
perspective, the instinct that prompted the ancient Greek
mathematicians to study conics becomes even more remarkable.
Then
when we learn that it was the challenge of squaring the circle which
gave birth to the original interest in conics, something warns us to be
more careful about dismissing as fruitless any matter the greatest of
the Greeks found intellectually important, but instead strive to
reexamine and adjust our own idea of it.
According to
historians, leading mathematicians in Greek antiquity would "occupy"
themselves with this geometrical problem, known as the "quadrature".
What it involves, essentially, is constructing an ideal square with an
area equal to that of a given circle (where the radius of the circle is
one, an area equal to pi) and doing so in a finite number of operations
using only a straight edge and a compass. A practically identical
problem is the rectification of the circle: Constructing an ideal
straight line equal in length to the circumference of the circle.
Beginning
with Rene Descartes (1596 - 1650), advances in the methods of
coordinate geometry enabled mathematicians to translate any geometrical
problem into an equivalent algebra problem involving only numbers and
their relations. It was thereby established that a geometric problem
can be solved with a ruler and compass in a finite number of steps only
if its algebraic equivalent depends on a number that can be obtained
from a whole number by addition, subtraction, multiplication, division
or extraction of square roots. There are numbers that are beyond
algebraic, or transcendental; these cannot be the root of any algebraic
or constructible equation. In 1882 it was proved by Lindemann (1852
-1939) that pi is such a number. Therefore constructing the long sought
for square by means of a finite number of Euclidean operations alone is
impossible. Further pursuit of this problem - exactly as it has been
defined by the historians - is without question a dead end. But it was
a successful failure indeed. Those who chronicle the "completed"
history of the problem recount the instances where this doomed approach
to pi down through the centuries was nevertheless responsible for
important achievements in the development of mathematics.
Problems,
too, can evolve. The problem of squaring the circle has passed into an
ageometric one of understanding the mystery of pi, seeking some hidden
pattern in pi, some design, some relationship never noticed between the
circle and its area the square. This is no dead end. A man who has been
called the most knowledgable mathematician in 100 years occupied
himself with a mail-order supercomputer calculating pi to 2.26 billion
decimal places, looking for a system. The mathematical intuition that
fosters this dedication must be the same as that which drew the ancient
Greek scholars to this, even then, age old subject. That the Greeks
lacked the essential numeration system of positional decimal notation,
let alone calculators, needed to observe pi in this way argues all the
more eloquently for the importance of instinct in these matters.
And
what of their obsolete straight edge and compass, now discarded in the
continuing quest to fathom pi? Someone said there are no insoluble
problems, only misunderstood problems. So it may be with "squaring the
circle". Invariably when the problem is referred to the term "squaring"
the circle is used. Does this perhaps suggest an intrinsic tension with
the notion of a fixed square and a finite number of steps? Does it
invite consideration of a process, of something dynamic, continuing,
animated? Let us suppose the nature of the problem has indeed been
mistaken in a key respect. That of course pi is a never-ending ratio of
the way across a circle to the way around it, and will not be captured
in a fixed square constructed by the stipulated means. Let us suppose
that the true point of the ancient problem, instead, is to use
undivided ruler and compass as instruments to examine pi by
constructing a dynamic square, one that mirrors the unending decimal
expansion of pi. To track pi and express it in the form of a square
with straight edge and compass. We find to our fascination that there
is such a square. It may be said to vibrate.
Where would
one begin to construct a theoretical square whose area follows along
with the area of a forcing circle in the unending decimal dance of pi?
One promising starting point will be found in the famous golden section
of Eudoxus (c. 408-355 BC), which Kepler ranked as one of the two great
treasures of geometry, after the theorem of Pythagoras. Illustration 1.
If
we draw a line from the golden section C to the point D in Eudoxus' 1:2
right triangle, we may use that line CD as the semidiameter of an
interesting square. Illustration 2. The area of the square will of
course be one-half the square of twice the semidiameter, or 3.1671845 -
not all that bad a starting approximation of pi, actually. We need a
reference point. Imagine a perfect pi amounting to exactly 3.125. The
semi-diameter C'D of a square of area 3.125 in this construction would
start to the right of the golden section point, at .75 on the base of
the 1:2 right triangle, compared to the section point east of it at
.7639320. Let us call these values "base amounts", referring to the
base of the right triangle CBD that we use to determine the length of
the semidiameter of the sought for square. It will be seen that the
difference between these two points -measuring .0139320 - is the gulf
in which pi reverberates throughout infinitesimal eternity.
Now
let this small distance - .0139320 - be the hypotenuse of an inverted
1:2 right triangle, constructed with straight edge and compass as in
Proposition 12 of Euclid's Elements. Illustration 3. Henceforth, it is
possible to follow the successive decimal expansion of pi, each time
marking off a more exact base amount or starting point for the
semidiameter of the pursuing square, merely by manipulating the 1:2
right triangle form in one of four basic ways. Through operations
constructible with a straight edge and a compass - and a calculator to
give the decimals of pi and confirm the length of the segments being
marked off - one can arrive at ever more accurate base amount locations
for the terminus of the oscillating, note-like semidiameter.
Only
the first two steps need to be explained in order understand the rest.
In the first step, Illustration 4, we draw an altitude fg to the
hypotenuse of the east-facing 1:2 right triangle. This marks one-fifth
of the hypotenuse, gc'. We double that (hc') to get two-fifths -
.0055728 - and this is added to the right hand limit of .75 to arrive
at our third base amount - .7555728. This one step already gives us pi
of 3.1417, more accuracy than Archimedes (287 - 212 BC) achieved using
his method of exhaustion involving inscribed and circumscribed hexagons
of 96 sides. The addition here, .0055728, serves as the hypotenuse for
the next 1:2 right triangle in the series.
It is necessary
to reduce the size of the square. To do so, we face the inverted 1:2
right triangle west, meaning that we are subtracting from the base
amount and the area of the square so determined. This alternating
pattern, east - west, add - subtract, accounts for the ever diminishing
yet unending vibration in the square. We drop an altitude and mark off
a similar 1:2 right triangle one-fifth the size. Then (moving out from
the center line in the drawing) mark off one-half of that smaller
triangle, and one-half again, and yet a third time. Finally, we swing
the altitude of the last triangle down upon the hypotenuse, recalling
the first step in Eudoxus' original construction. This marks the next
base amount, which gives us pi of 3.141592 - probably more accuracy
than any earthly engineering application would ever require. (The
decrement will form the first hypotenuse in the next step.)
From
here on, the appropriate manipulation of the 1:2 right triangles is
shown in the drawing (Illustration 5). In 42 east/west operations (79
steps in all) we have pi to 35 decimal places. It looks like a series
of semaphore signals. (Best to print Illustration 5.)
The idea of an alternating infinite series of plus and minus terms
approaching pi is not new. The simple series pi/4 = 1/1 - 1/3 + 1/5 -
1/7 + 1/9 . . . is named for Leibniz (1646 - 1716), although it was
known earlier. Histories of this problem have reported no suggestion by
Leibniz or others of such a plus/minus formula for a dimension of a
square (or any other figure) whose area approaches pi, however. There
is also the matter of speed of convergence. As noted, the second step
in the method discussed here (Illustration 6. gives a formula
approaching the square root of [pi/2 - 1] ) yields pi correct to six
decimals.
In the Leibniz series you would have pi to only 3
correct decimal places after seven thousand alternate steps. The
series [pi - 3]/4 = 1/(2 x 3 x 4) - 1/(4 x 5 x 6) + 1/(6 x 7 x 8)
. . .gives pi to 6 decimals in about 110 steps. The series[pi/6] =
[square root 1/3] . [1/(30 x 1) - 1/(31 x 3) + 1/(32 x 5) - 1/(33 x 7)
+ 1/(34 x 9) . . .] gives 6 places in only 13 steps. But neither do
these latter two series relate to any square. They may be said to play
hopscotch back and forth over pi, but no geometric image is imparted. Mathematicians
have had no success searching for a pattern throughout more than 2
billion decimal digits of pi. The straight edge and compass no longer
play any role at all in this modern quest. The kind of method discussed
here offers a different vantage point for observing pi. It reintroduces
the classical straight edge and compass, redefining the problem of
squaring the circle to avoid Lindemann's dead end. Perhaps it will
yield something interesting, maybe even some tool needed for solution
of a scientific problem. A mathematical explanation of why 4 relations
of the 1:2 right triangle can be arranged in an alternating series to
approach square root (pi/2) - 1 would be intrinsically valuable.
Finally,
a thought about proportion. If the line AB in Illustration 2 was the
distance light travels in one thousand years, the increment subtracted
in the last step in the series in Illustration 6 would be near the
scale of the subatomic particle known as the quark. Yet we have barely
begun to express pi with straight edge and compass. The prospect
recalls a passage from the Pensees of Blaise Pascal (1623-1662):
But,
to offer him another prodigy equally astounding, let him look into the
tiniest things he knows. Let a mite show him in its minute body
incomparably more minute parts, legs with joints, veins in its legs,
blood in the veins, humours in the blood, drops in the humours, vapours
in the drops; let him divide these things still further until he has
exhausted his powers of imagination, and let the last thing he comes
down to now be the subject of our discourse. He will perhaps think that
this is the ultimate of minuteness in nature. I want to show him a new
abyss. I want to depict to him not only the visible universe, but all
the conceivable immensity of nature enclosed in this miniature atom.
Let him see there an infinity of universes, each with its firmament,
its planets, its earth, in the same proportions as in the visible
world, and on that earth animals, and finally mites, in which he will
find again the same results as in the first; and finding the same thing
yet again in the others, he will be lost in such wonders, as astounding
in their minuteness as the others in their amplitude. For who will not
marvel that our body, a moment ago imperceptible in a universe, itself
imperceptible in the bosom of the whole, should now be a colossus, a
world, or rather a whole, compared to the nothingness beyond our reach?
Anyone who considers himself in this way will be terrified at himself,
and, seeing his mass, as given him by nature, supporting him between
these two abysses of infinity and nothingness, will tremble at these
marvels. I believe that with his curiosity changing into wonder he will
be more disposed to contemplate them in silence than investigate them
with presumption.
See also: How to Unroll a Circle and Hyperbolic
Trisection and the Spectrum of Regular Polygons
Home
Page: Song
of Songs.net
email:
webmaster@song-of-songs.net
Copyright © 2007 - 2009, by Thomas Call.
|